There is a newer version available for this article. View latest version

    • JF
Views

2,200

Downloads

328

Peer reviewers

6

Make action
PDF

Field

Mathematics

Subfield

Mathematical Physics

Open Peer Review

Preprint

2.50 | 6 peer reviewers

CC BY

The Fallacy in the Paradox of Achilles and the Tortoise

James Q. Feng1

Affiliation

Highly-cited researcher
  1. Optomec (United States), Albuquerque, United States

Abstract

Zeno’s ancient paradox depicts a race between swift Achilles and a slow tortoise with a head start. Zeno argued that Achilles could never overtake the tortoise, as at each step Achilles arrived at the tortoise’s former position, the tortoise had already moved ahead. Though Zeno’s premise is valid, his conclusion that Achilles can “never” pass the tortoise relies on equating infinite steps with an infinite amount of time. By modeling the sequence of events in terms of a converging geometric series, this paper shows that such an infinite number of events sum up to a finite distance traversed in finite time. The paradox stems from confusion between an infinite number of events, which can happen in a finite time interval, and an infinite amount of time. The fallacy is clarified by recognizing that the infinite number of events can be crammed into a finite time interval. At a given speed difference after a finite amount of time, Achilles will have completed the infinite series of gaps and passed the tortoise.

Correspondence: papers@team.qeios.com — Qeios will forward to the authors

One of the most famous paradoxes is that of Zeno’s Achilles and the tortoise. An ancient Greek philosopher, Zeno of Elea, imagined a race between the mythical warrior Achilles and a tortoise. To make it seem like a fair race, Achilles allows the tortoise to start at a distance ahead of him. When Achilles reaches the point where the tortoise started, the tortoise has moved ahead of him, and each time Achilles reaches the tortoise’s former position, the tortoise is further down the track. Thus, the tortoise is always ahead of Achilles, which leads to the conclusion that Achilles would never be able to run past the naturally slow tortoise—obviously against the common-sense-based expectation.

Zeno’s premise is that “For Achilles to catch the tortoise, he must run to the tortoise’s initial place when the tortoise would have advanced to a new place, to where Achilles must run to reach when the tortoise would have advanced further ahead to a newer place, and so on.” There is nothing wrong with Zeno’s premise, which can be mathematically expressed as follows.

If Achilles starts at x = 0, running at a constant speed of sA, while the tortoise starts at x = x0, moving at a constant speed of sT, he should reach x = x0 at time t0 = x0 / sA when the tortoise would have moved to a new place at x = x1 = x0 + sT t0 = x0 (1 + sT / sA) further ahead. Then, Achilles should reach x = x1 at time t1 = x1 / sA = (x0 / sA) (1 + sT / sA), when the tortoise would have moved to a newer place at x = x2 = x0 + sT t1 = x0 [1 + (sT / sA) (1 + sT / sA)] further ahead, and so on. Thus, Achilles should reach x = xn at time

tn = (x0 / sA) * [1 + (sT / sA) + (sT / sA)2 + … + (sT / sA)n] = (x0 / sA) [1 - (sT / sA)n+1] / (1 - sT / sA)

as a geometric series, with

xn = x0 [1 - (sT / sA)n+1] / (1 - sT / sA),

where the speed of Achilles and the speed of the tortoise,

sA = xn / tn and sT = (xn+1 - x0) / tn

are constants.

Given that the speed ratio sT / sA < 1, as Achilles is faster than the tortoise, we have

t = (x0 / sA) / (1 - sT / sA) and x = x0 / (1 - sT / sA) as n —> ∞,

which suggests that Achilles should catch up with the tortoise at x = x, when t = t; thereafter, Achilles would be running ahead of the tortoise. For example, if x0 = 1 and sT / sA = 1/2 (or 1/3, 1/5, 1/10), assuming sT = 1, we should have t = 1 (or 1/2, 1/4, 1/9) and x = 2 (or 3/2, 5/4, 10/9).

Although Zeno presented his premise flawlessly – i.e., the tortoise would be ahead of Achilles at any time t = tn < t, no matter how large the value of n becomes – his conclusion that Achilles would never be able to run past the tortoise is mistakenly based on an implication that n —> ∞ equates to tn —> ∞, means that something could not happen at any time. Yet, “unbounded n corresponds to unbounded tn” was not included in Zeno’s premise. In fact, a large n in tn cannot mean that the value of tn must be large. With sT / sA < 1, tn < t = (x0 / sA) / (1 - sT / sA) is always finite, beyond which (as the clock ticks and time moves forward when t > t) Achilles will be ahead of the tortoise.

The paradox of Zeno’s Achilles and the tortoise has been regarded as a supertask, consisting of an infinite sequence of subtasks to be completed in a finite amount of time. Whether a supertask can possibly be completed has been a subject of academic debate (e.g., Black 1951; Wisdom 1952; Chihara 1965; McLaughlin and Miller 1992; Alper and Bridger 1997; Salmon 1998; Peijnenburg and Atkinson 2008; Ardourel 2015). The difficulty appears to come from the intuition that an infinite number of subtasks could take forever to complete. But in the case of Zeno’s Achilles and the tortoise, the completion of those infinite steps seems possible when one recognizes the fact that an infinite number of subtasks may not necessarily need an infinite amount of time to complete.

In philosophy, the concepts of space and time have been related to the relative locations of objects and sequences of events. It has become common sense to measure the distance between objects with yardsticks of constant length and to create units of time using a time interval between two specific and regular events, such as repeated positions of the Sun in the sky throughout the day. In some ways, Zeno tricked us by implying the time measurement with events of a shrinking time interval, presenting an illusion of an infinite sequence of events occurring through an infinitely long time. As time is traditionally presented as a dense real number axis, a finite time interval contains an infinite number of real numbers to offer opportunities for creating illusions with an infinite sequence of events crammed into a finite small time interval. Another similar paradox of Zeno describes the runner Achilles starting at the starting line of a track and running past half of the distance to the finish line. He then runs past half of the remaining distance and continues in this way over and over without end, getting ever closer to the finish line but never able to reach it. It has the same type of logical fallacy as that in Achilles and the tortoise.

Author’s Bio

Now an independent scientist, Dr. James Q. Feng was a Principal Engineer at Optomec, with extensive knowledge in Applied Physics and Mathematics. He graduated from Tsinghua University in Beijing before pursuing his PhD degree at the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign in the United States. After a few years of postdoctoral work at the University of Minnesota and Oak Ridge National Laboratory, Dr. Feng had worked at various industrial companies such as Xerox Corporation, Clear Science Corp, Boston Scientific Corporation, and Optomec, Inc. Over the years, he has published more than 65 peer-reviewed journal articles and holds more than 20 granted U.S. Patents.

References

  • Ardourel, V. (2015). A discrete solution for the paradox of Achilles and the tortoise. Synthese, 192(9), 2843-2861.
  • Alper, J. S., & Bridger, M. (1997). Mathematics, models, and Zeno’s paradoxes of motion. Synthese, 110, 143-166.
  • Black, M. (1951). Achilles and the tortoise. Analysis, 11(5), 91-101.
  • Chihara, C. S. (1965). On the possibility of completing an infinite process. The Philosophical Review, 74(1), 74-87.
  • McLaughlin, W. I., & Miller, S. L. (1992). An epistemological use of nonstandard analysis to answer Zeno’s objections against motion. Synthese, 92(3), 371-384.
  • Peijnenburg, J., & Atkinson, D. (2008). Achilles, the tortoise, and colliding balls. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 25(3), 187-201.
  • Salmon, W. (1998). A contemporary look at Zeno’s paradoxes: An excerpt from space, time and motion. In Metaphysics: The Big Questions, van Inwagen and Zimmerman (Eds.), Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
  • Wisdom, J. O. (1952). Achilles on a physical racecourse. Analysis, 12(3), 67-72.

Open Peer Review